West of Eden,
A Science of Good and Evil,
Experiments in Consciousness,
Epilogue
excerpted from the book
The End of Faith
Religion, Terror, and the Future
of Reason
by Sam Harris
WW Norton, 2004
West of Eden
p153
The degree to which religious ideas still determine government
policies specially those of the United States-presents a grave
danger to everyone. It has been widely reported, for instance,
that Ronald Reagan perceived the paroxysms in the Middle East
through the lens of biblical prophecy. He went so far as to include
men like Jerry Falwell and Hal Lindsey in his national security
briefings.' It should go without saying that theirs are not the
sober minds one wants consulted about the deployment of nuclear
weaponry. For many years U.S. policy in the Middle East has been
shaped, at least in part, by the interests that fundamentalist
Christians have in the future of a Jewish state. Christian "support
for Israel" is, in fact, an example of religious cynicism
so transcendental as to go almost unnoticed in our political discourse.
Fundamentalist Christians support Israel because they believe
that the final consolidation of Jewish power in the Holy Land-specifically,
the rebuilding of Solomon's temple-will usher in both the Second
Coming of Christ and the final destruction of the Jews. Such smiling
anticipations of genocide seem to have presided over the Jewish
state from its first moments: the first international support
for the Jewish return to Palestine, Britain's Balfour Declaration
of 1917, was inspired, at least in part, by a conscious conformity
to biblical prophecy. These intrusions of eschatology into modern
politics suggest that the dangers of religious faith can scarcely
be overstated. Millions of Christians and Muslims now organize
their lives around prophetic traditions that will only find fulfillment
once rivers of blood begin flowing from Jerusalem.
The Eternal Legislator
Many members of the U.S. government currently
view their professional responsibilities in religious terms. Consider
the case of Roy Moore, chief justice of the Alabama Supreme Court.
Finding himself confronted by the sixth-highest murder rate in
the nation, justice Moore thought it expedient to install a two-and-a-half-ton
monument of the Ten Commandments in the rotunda of the state courthouse
in Montgomery. Almost no one disputes that this was a violation
of the spirit (if not the letter) of the "establishment"
clause of the First Amendment to the U.S. Constitution. When a
federal court ordered Justice Moore to remove the monument, he
refused. Not wanting to have an obvious hand in actually separating
church and state, the U.S. Congress amended an appropriations
bill to ensure that federal funds could not be used for the monument's
removal. Attorney General John Ashcroft, whose sole business is
to enforce the nation's laws, maintained a pious silence all the
while. This was not surprising, given that when he does speak,
he is in the habit of saying things like "We are a nation
called to defend freedom-freedom that is not the grant of any
government or document, but is our endowment from God."'
According to a Gallup poll, Ashcroft and the Congress were on
firm ground as far as the American people were concerned, because
78 percent of those polled objected to the removal of the monument.
One wonders whether Moore, Ashcroft, the U.S. Congress, and three-quarters
of the American people would like to see the punishments for breaking
these hallowed commandments also specified in marble and placed
in our nation's courts. What, after all, is the punishment for
taking the Lord's name in vain? It happens to be death (Leviticus
24:16). What is the punishment for working on the Sabbath? Also
death (Exodus 31:15). What is the punishment for cursing one's
father or mother? Death again (Exodus 21:17). What is the punishment
for adultery? You're catching on (Leviticus 20:10). While the
commandments themselves are difficult to remember (especially
since chapters 20 and 34 of Exodus provide us with incompatible
lists), the penalty for breaking them is simplicity itself.
p155
... 40 percent of those who eventually voted for Bush were white
evangelicals.
p156
... 65 percent of [Americans] are quite certain that Satan exists.
p156
In January of 2002, Supreme Court Justice Antonin Scalia, a devout
Catholic, delivered a speech at the University of Chicago Divinity
School on the subject of the death penalty. I quote Scalia at
some length, because his remarks reveal just how close we are
to living in a theocracy:
This is not the Old Testament, I emphasize,
but St. Paul.... [T]he core of his message is that government-however
you want to limit that concept-derives its moral authority from
God. Indeed, it seems to me that the more Christian a country
is the less likely it is to regard the death penalty as immoral
.... I attribute that to the fact that, for the believing Christian,
death is no big deal. Intentionally killing an innocent person
is a big deal: it is a grave sin, which causes one to lose his
soul. But losing this life, in exchange for the next? ... For
the nonbeliever, on the other hand, to deprive a man of his life
is to end his existence. What a horrible act! .
The reaction of people of faith to this
tendency of democracy to obscure the divine authority behind government
should not be resignation to it, but the resolution to combat
it as effectively as possible. We have done that in this country
(and continental Europe has not) by preserving in our public life
many visible reminders that-in the words of a Supreme Court opinion
from the 1940s-"we are a religious people, whose institutions
presuppose a Supreme Being." . . . All this, as I say, is
most unEuropean, and helps explain why our people are more inclined
to understand, as St. Paul did, that government carries the sword
as "the minister of God," to "execute wrath"
upon the evildoer.
All of this should be terrifying to anyone
who expects that reason will prevail in the inner sanctums of
power in the West. Scalia is right to observe that what a person
believes happens after death determines his view of it-and, therefore,
his ethics. Although he is a Catholic, Scalia differs from the
pope on the subject of capital punishment, but then so do a majority
of Americans (74 percent). It is remarkable that we are the last
civilized nation to put "evildoers" to death, and Justice
Scalia rightly attributes this to our style of religiosity.
p158
... men who believe that we already have God's eternal decrees
on paper-have been inoculated against doubts on this subject or,
indeed, against the nuances of a scientific worldview. It is not
surprising that Scalia is the kind of judge that President Bush
has sought to appoint to the federal courts. 18 Scalia supports
the use of capital punishment even in cases where the defendant
is acknowledged to be mentally retarded. He also upholds state
sodomy laws (in this case, even when they are applied in an exclusive
and discriminating way to homosexuals) 20 Needless to say, Scalia
has found legal reasons to insist that the Supreme Court not leaven
the religious dogmatism of the states, but he leaves little doubt
that he looks to Saint Paul, and perhaps to the barbarous author
of Leviticus, for guidance on these matters.
The War on Sin
p159
It is no accident that people of faith often want to curtail the
private freedoms of others. This impulse has less to do with the
history of religion and more to do with its logic, because the
very idea of privacy is incompatible with the existence of God.
If God sees and knows all things, and remains so provincial a
creature as to be scandalized by certain sexual behaviors or states
of the brain, then what people do in the privacy of their own
homes, though it may not have the slightest implication for their
behavior in public, will still be a matter of public concern for
people of faith.
A variety of religious notions of wrongdoing
can be seen converging here-concerns over nonprocreative sexuality
and idolatry especially-and these seem to have given many of us
the sense that it is ethical to punish people, often severely,
for engaging in private behavior that harms no one. Like most
costly examples of irrationality, in which human happiness has
been blindly subverted for generations, the role of religion here
is both explicit and foundational. To see that our laws against
"vice" have actually nothing to do with keeping people
from coming to physical or psychological harm, and everything
to do with not angering God, we need only consider that oral or
anal sex between consenting adults remains a criminal offense
in thirteen states. Four of the states (Texas, Kansas, Oklahoma,
and Missouri) prohibit these acts between same-sex couples and,
therefore, effectively prohibit homosexuality. The other nine
ban consensual sodomy for everyone (these places of equity are
Alabama, Florida, Idaho, Louisiana, Mississippi, North Carolina,
South Carolina, Utah, and Virginia).23 One does not have to be
a demographer to grasp that the impulse to prosecute consenting
adults for nonprocreative sexual behavior will correlate rather
strongly with religious faith.
The influence of faith on our criminal
laws comes at a remarkable price. Consider the case of drugs.
As it happens, there are many substances-many of them naturally
occurring-the consumption of which leads to transient states of
inordinate pleasure. Occasionally, it is true, they lead to transient
states of misery as well, but there is no doubt that pleasure
is the norm, otherwise human beings would not have felt the continual
desire to take such substances for millennia. Of course, pleasure
is precisely the problem with these substances, since pleasure
and piety have always had an uneasy relationship.
When one looks at our drug laws-indeed,
at our vice laws altogether-the only organizing principle that
appears to make sense of them is that anything which might radically
eclipse prayer or procreative sexuality as a source of pleasure
has been outlawed. In particular, any drug (LSD, mescaline, psilocybin,
DMT, MDMA, marijuana, etc.) to which spiritual or religious significance
has been ascribed by its users has been prohibited. Concerns about
the health of our citizens, or about their productivity, are red
herrings in this debate, as the legality of alcohol and cigarettes
attests.
The fact that people are being prosecuted
and imprisoned for using marijuana, while alcohol remains a staple
commodity, is surely the reductio ad absurdum of any notion that
our drug laws are designed to keep people from harming themselves
or others. Alcohol is by any measure the more dangerous substance.
p162
Our prohibition of certain substances has led thousands of otherwise
productive and law-abiding men and women to be locked away for
decades at a stretch, sometimes for life. Their children have
become wards of the state. As if such cascading horror were not
disturbing enough, violent criminals-murders, rapists, and child
molesters-are regularly paroled to make room for them. Here we
appear to have overstepped the banality of evil and plunged to
the absurdity at its depths.
The consequences of our irrationality
on this front are so egregious that they bear closer examination.
Each year, over 1.5 million men and women are arrested in the
United States because of our drug laws. At this moment, somewhere
on the order of 400,000 men and women languish in U.S. prisons
for nonviolent drug offenses. One million others are currently
on probation. More people are imprisoned for nonviolent drug offenses
in the United States than are incarcerated, for any reason, in
all of Western Europe (which has a larger population).
p163
The problem with the prohibition of any desirable commodity is
/ money. The United Nations values the drug trade at $400 billion
a year. This exceeds the annual budget for the U.S. Department
of Defense. If this figure is correct, the trade in illegal drugs
constitutes 8 percent of all international commerce (while the
sale of textiles makes up 7.5 percent and motor vehicles just
5.3 percent).35 And yet, prohibition itself is what makes the
manufacture and sale of drugs so extraordinarily profitable. Those
who earn their living in this way enjoy a 5,000 to 20,000 percent
return on their investment, tax-free. Every relevant indicator
of the drug trade rates of drug use and interdiction, estimates
of production, the purity of drugs on the street, etc.-shows that
the government can do nothing to stop it as long as such profits
exist (indeed, these profits are highly corrupting of law enforcement
in any case). The crimes of the addict, to finance the stratospheric
cost of his lifestyle, and the crimes of the dealer, to protect
both his territory and his goods, are likewise the results of
prohibition. A final irony, which seems good enough to be the
work of Satan himself, is that the market we have created by our
drug laws has become a steady source of revenue for terrorist
organizations ...
p164
Anyone who believes that God is watching us from beyond the stars
will feel that punishing peaceful men and women for their private
pleasure is perfectly reasonable. We are now in the twenty-first
century. Perhaps we should have better reasons for depriving our
neighbors of their liberty at gunpoint. Given the magnitude of
the real problems that confront us-terrorism, nuclear proliferation,
the spread of infectious disease, failing infrastructure, lack
of adequate funds for education and health care, etc.--our war
on sin is so outrageously unwise as to almost defy rational comment.
p167
President Bush recent decided to cut off funding to any overseas
family-planning group that provides information on abortion. According
to the New York Times, this "has effectively stopped condom
provision to 16 countries and reduced it in 13 others, including
some with the world's highest rates of AIDS infection." Under
the influence of Christian notions of the sinfulness of sex outside
of marriage, the U.S. government has required that one-third of
its AIDS prevention funds allocated to Africa be squandered on
teaching abstinence rather than condom use. It is no exaggeration
to say that millions could die as a direct result of this single
efflorescence of religious dogmatism.
p168
Faith drives a wedge between ethics and suffering. Where certain
actions cause no suffering at all, religious dogmatists still
maintain that they are evil and worthy of punishment (sodomy,
marijuana use, homosexuality, the killing of blastocysts, etc.).
And yet, where suffering and death are found in abundance their
causes are often deemed to be good (withholding funds for family
planning in the third world, prosecuting nonviolent drug offenders,
preventing stem-cell research, etc). This inversion of priorities
not only victimizes innocent people and squanders scarce resources;
it completely falsifies our ethics. It is time we found a more
reasonable approach to answering questions of right and wrong.
p172
We ... do not need religious ideas to motivate us to live ethical
lives. Once we begin thinking seriously about happiness and suffering,
we find that our religious traditions are no more reliable on
questions of ethics than they have been on scientific questions
generally.
p172
The perverse wonder of evolution is this: the very mechanisms
that create the incredible beauty and diversity of the living
world guarantee monstrosity and death. The child born without
limbs, the sightless fly, the vanished species-these are nothing
less than Mother Nature caught in the act of throwing her clay.
No perfect God could maintain such incongruities. It is worth
remembering that if God created the world and all things in it,
he created smallpox, plague, and filariasis.
p176
Christopher Hitchens
"What can be asserted without evidence can also be dismissed
without evidence."
p176
How is it ... that a Nazi guard could return each day from his
labors at the crematoria and be a loving father to his children?
The answer is surprisingly straightforward: the Jews he spent
the day torturing and killing were not objects of his moral concern.
Not only were they outside his moral community; they were antithetical
to it. His beliefs about Jews inured him to the natural human
sympathies that might have otherwise prevented such behavior.
Unfortunately, religion casts more shadows
than light on this terrain. Rather than find real reasons for
human solidarity, faith offers us a solidarity born of tribal
and tribalizing fictions. As we have seen, religion is one of
the great limiters of moral identity, since most believers differentiate
themselves, in moral terms, from those who do not share their
faith. No other ideology is so eloquent on the subject of what
divides one moral community from another. Once a person accepts
the premises upon which most religious identities are built, the
withdrawal of his moral concern from those who do not share these
premises follows quite naturally. Needless to say, the suffering
of those who are destined for hell can never be as problematic
as the suffering of the righteous. If certain people can't see
the unique wisdom and sanctity of my religion, if their hearts
are so beclouded by sin, what concern is it of mine if others
mistreat them? They have been cursed by the very God who made
the world and all things in it. Their search for happiness was
simply doomed from the start.
p185
For ethics to matter to us, the happiness and suffering of others
must matter to us.
p186
To treat others ethically is to act out of concern for their happiness
and suffering. It is, as Kant observed, to treat them as ends
in themselves rather than as a means to some further end. Many
ethical injunctions converge here-Kant's categorical imperative,
Jesus' golden rule-but the basic facts are these: we experience
happiness and suffering ourselves; we encounter others in the
world and recognize that they experience happiness and suffering
as well; we soon discover that "love" is largely a matter
of wishing that others experience happiness rather than suffering
...
p187
Consider the practice of "honor killing" that persists
throughout] much of Africa, the Middle East, and Southeast Asia.
We live in a world in which women and girls are regularly murdered
by their male relatives for perceived sexual indiscretions-ranging
from merely speaking to a man without permission to falling victim
of rape. Coverage of these atrocities in the Western media generally
refers to them as a "tribal" practice, although they
almost invariably occur in a Muslim context. Whether we call the
beliefs that inspire this behavior "tribal" or "religious"
is immaterial; the problem is clearly a product of what men in
these societies believe about shame and honor, about the role
of women, and about female sexuality.
One consequence of these beliefs has been
to promote rape as a weapon of war. No doubt there are more creaturely,
and less calculating, motives for soldiers to commit rape on a
massive scale, but it cannot be denied that male beliefs about
"honor" have made it a brilliant instrument of psychological
and cultural oppression. Rape has become a means through which
the taboos of a community can be used to rend it from within.
Consider the Bosnian women systematically raped by Serbs: one
might have thought that since many of their male relatives could
not escape getting killed, it would be only reasonable to concede
that the women themselves could not escape getting raped. But
such flights of ethical intelligence cannot be made with a sufficient
payload of unjustified belief-in this case, belief in the intrinsic
sinfulness of women, in the importance of virginity prior to marriage,
and in the shamefulness of being raped. Needless to say, similar
failures of compassion have a venerable pedigree in the Christian
West. Augustine, for instance, when considering the moral stature
of virgins who had been raped by the Goths, wondered whether they
had not been "unduly puffed up by [their] integrity, continence
and chastity." Perhaps they suffered "some lurking infirmity
which might have betrayed them into proud and contemptuous bearing,
had they not been subjected to the humiliation that befell them.
" Perhaps, in other words, they deserved it.
Given the requisite beliefs about "honor,"
a man will be desperate to kill his daughter upon learning that
she was raped. The same angel of compassion can be expected to
visit her brothers as well. Such killings are not at all uncommon
in places like Jordan, Egypt, Lebanon, Pakistan, Iraq, the Gaza
Strip, and the West Bank. In these parts of the world, a girl
of any age who gets raped has brought shame upon her family. Luckily,
this shame is not indelible and can be readily expunged with her
blood. The subsequent ritual is inevitably a low-tech affair,
as none of these societies have devised a system for administering
lethal injections for the crime of bringing shame upon one's family.
The girl either has her throat cut, or she is dowsed with gasoline
and set on fire, or she is shot. The jail sentences for these
men, if they are prosecuted at all, are invariably short. Many
are considered heroes in their communities.
What can we say about this behavior? Can
we say that Middle Eastern men who are murderously obsessed with
female sexual purity actually love their wives, daughters, and
sisters less than American or European men do? Of course, we can.
And what is truly incredible about the state of our discourse
is that such a claim is not only controversial but actually unutterable
in most contexts.
Where's the proof that these men are less
capable of love than the rest of us? Well, where would the proof
be if a person behaved this way in our own society? Where's the
proof that the person who shot JFK didn't really love him? All
the proof we need came from the book depository. We know how the
word "love" functions in our discourse. We have all
felt love, have failed to feel it, and have occasionally felt
its antithesis. Even if we don't harbor the slightest sympathy
for their notion of "honor," we know what these honor
killers are up to-and it is not a matter of expressing their love
for the women in their lives. Of course, honor killing is merely
one facet in that terrible kaleidoscope that is the untutored,
male imagination: dowry deaths and bride burnings, female infanticide,
acid attacks, female genital mutilation, sexual slavery-these
and other joys await unlucky women throughout much of the world.
There is no doubt that certain beliefs are incompatible with love,
and this notion of "honor" is among them.
p190
Any culture that raises men and boys to kill unlucky girls, rather
I than comfort them, is a culture that has managed to retard the
growth of love. Such societies, of course, regularly fail to teach
their inhabitants many other things-like how to read. Not learning
how to read is not another style of literacy, and not learning
to see others as ends in themselves is not another style of ethics.
It is a failure ethics.
p194
What, after all, is "collateral damage" but the inadvertent
torture of innocent men, women, and children? Whenever we consent
to drop bombs, we do so with the knowledge that some number of
children will be blinded, disemboweled, paralyzed, orphaned, and
killed by them. It is curious that while the torture of Osama
bin Laden himself could be expected to provoke convulsions of
conscience among our leaders, the unintended (though perfectly
foreseeable, and therefore accepted) slaughter of children does
not.
So we can now ask, if we are willing to
act in a way that guarantees the misery and death of some considerable
number of innocent children, why spare the rod with suspected
terrorists? What is the difference between pursuing a course of
action where we run the risk of inadvertently subjecting some
innocent men to torture, and pursuing one in which we will inadvertently
kill far greater numbers of innocent men, women, and children?
Rather, it seems obvious that the misapplication of torture should
be far less troubling to us than collateral damage: there are,
after all, no infants interned at Guantanamo Bay, just rather
scrofulous young men, many of whom were caught in the very act
of trying to kill our soldiers. Torture need not even impose a
significant risk of death or permanent injury on its victims;
while the collaterally damaged are, almost by definition, crippled
or killed. The ethical divide that seems to be opening up here
suggests that those who are willing to drop bombs might want to
abduct the nearest and dearest of suspected terrorists-their wives,
mothers, and daughters-and torture them as well, assuming anything
profitable to our side might come of it. Admittedly, this would
be a ghastly result to have reached by logical argument, and we
will want to find some way of escaping it.
In this context, we should note that many
variables influence our feelings about an act of physical violence,
as well as our intuitions about its ethical status. As Clover
points out, "in modern war, what is most shocking is a poor
guide to what is most harmful." To learn that one's grandfather
flew a bombing mission over Dresden in the Second World War is
one thing; to hear that he killed five little girls and their
mother with a shovel is another. We can be sure that he would
have killed more women and girls by dropping bombs from pristine
heights, and they are likely to have died equally horrible deaths,
but his culpability would not appear the same. Indeed, we seem
to know, intuitively, that it would take a different kind of person
to perpetrate violence of the latter sort. And, as we might expect,
the psychological effects of participating in these types of violence
are generally distinct. Consider the following account of a Soviet
soldier in Afghanistan: "It's frightening and unpleasant
to have to kill, you think, but you soon realize that what you
really find objectionable is shooting someone point-blank. Killing
en masse, in a group, is exciting, even-and I've seen this myself-fun.
This is not to say that no one has ever enjoyed killing people
up close; it is just that we all recognize that such enjoyment
requires an unusual degree of callousness to the suffering of
others.
It is possible that we are simply unequipped
to rectify this disparity-to be, in Glover's terms, most shocked
by what is most harmful. A biological rationale is not hard to
find, as millions of years on the African veldt could not possibly
have selected for an ability to make emotional sense of twenty-first-century
horror. That our Paleolithic genes now have chemical, biological,
and nuclear weapons at their disposal is, from the point of view
of our evolution, little different from our having delivered this
technology into the hands of chimps. The difference between killing
one man and killing a thousand just doesn't seem as salient to
us as it should. And, as Clover observes, in many cases we will
find the former far more disturbing. Three million souls can be
starved and murdered in the Congo, and our Argus-eyed media scarcely
blink. When a princess dies in a car accident, however, a quarter
of the earth's population falls prostrate with grief. Perhaps
we are unable to feel what we must feel in order to change the
world.
p199
The False Choice of Pacifism
Pacifism is generally considered to be
a morally unassailable position to take with respect to human
violence. The worst that is said of it, generally, is that it
is a difficult position to maintain in practice. It is almost
never branded as flagrantly immoral, which I believe it is. While
it can seem noble enough when the stakes are low, pacifism is
ultimately nothing more than a willingness to die, and to let
others die, at the pleasure of the world's thugs. It should be
enough to note that a single sociopath, armed with nothing more
than a knife, could exterminate a city full of pacifists j There
is no doubt that such sociopaths exist, and they are generally
better armed. Fearing that the above reflections on torture may
offer a potent argument for pacifism, I would like to briefly
state why I believe we must accept the fact that violence (or
its threat) is often an ethical necessity.
p202
Gandhi was undoubtedly the twentieth century's most influential
pacifist. The success he enjoyed in forcing the British Empire
to withdraw from the Indian subcontinent brought pacifism down
from the ethers of religious precept and gave it new political
relevance. Pacifism in this form no doubt required considerable
bravery from its practitioners and constituted a direct confrontation
with injustice. As such, it had far more moral integrity than
did my stratagem above. It is clear, however, that Gandhi's nonviolence
can be applied to only a limited range of human conflict. We would
do well to reflect on Gandhi's remedy for the Holocaust: he believed
that the Jews should have committed mass suicide, because this
"would have aroused the world and the people of Germany to
Hitler's violence." We might wonder what a world full of
pacifists would have done once it had grown "aroused"-commit
suicide as well?
Gandhi was a religious dogmatist, of course,
but his remedy for the Holocaust seems ethically suspect even
if one accepts the metaphysical premises upon which it was based.
If we grant the law of karma and rebirth to which Gandhi subscribed,
his pacifism still seems highly immoral. Why should it be thought
ethical to safeguard one's own happiness (or even the happiness
of others) in the next life at the expense of the manifest agony
of children in this one? Gandhi's was a world in which millions
more would have died in the hopes that the Nazis would have one
day doubted the goodness of their Thousand Year Reich. Ours is
a world in which bombs must occasionally fall where such doubts
are in short supply. Here we come upon a terrible facet of ethically
asymmetric warfare: when your enemy has no scruples, your own
scruples become another weapon in his hand.
It is, as yet, unclear what it will mean
to win our war on "terrorism"-or whether the religious
barbarism that animates our enemies can ever be finally purged
from our world-but it is all too obvious what it would mean to
lose it. Life under the Taliban is, to a first approximation,
what millions of Muslims around the world want to impose on the
rest of us. They long to establish a society in which-when times
are good-women will remain vanquished and invisible, and anyone
given to spiritual, intellectual, or sexual freedom will be slaughtered
before crowds of sullen, uneducated men. This, needless to say,
is a vision of life worth resisting. We cannot let our qualms
over collateral damage paralyze us because our enemies know no
such qualms. Theirs is a kill-the-children-first approach to war,
and we ignore the fundamental difference between their violence
and our own at our peril. Given the proliferation of weaponry
in our world, we no longer have the option of waging this war
with swords. It seems certain that collateral damage, of various
sorts, will be a part of our future for many years to come.
The Wisdom of the East
p215
... when the great philosopher mystics of the East are weighed
against the patriarchs of the Western philosophical aft] theological
traditions, the difference is unmistakable: Buddha, Shankara,
Padmasambhava, Nagarjuna, Longchenpa, and countless others down
to the present have no equivalents in the West. In spiritual terms,
we appear to have been standing on the shoulders of dwarfs. It
is little wonder, therefore, that many Western scholars have found
the view within rather unremarkable."
p221
Religion is nothing more than bad concepts held in place of good
ones for all time. It is the denial-at once full of hope and full
of fear-of the vastitude of human ignorance.
A kernel of truth lurks at the heart of
religion, because spiritual experience, ethical behavior, and
strong communities are essential for human happiness. And yet
our religious traditions are intellectually defunct and politically
ruinous. While spiritual experience is clearly a natural propensity
of the human mind, we need not believe anything on insufficient
evidence to actualize it. Clearly, it must be possible to bring
reason, spirituality, and ethics together in our thinking about
the world. This would be the beginning of a rational approach
to our deepest personal concerns. It would also be the end of
faith.
Epilogue
p223
While religious faith is the one species of human ignorance that
will not admit of even the possibility of correction, it is still
sheltered from criticism in every corner of our culture. Forsaking
all valid sources of information about this world (both spiritual
and mundane), our religions have seized upon ancient taboos and
prescientific fancies as though they held ultimate metaphysical
significance. Books that embrace the narrowest spectrum of political,
moral, scientific, and spiritual understanding, books that, by
their antiquity alone, offer us the most dilute wisdom with respect
to the present-are still dogmatically thrust upon us as the final
word on matters of the greatest significance. In the best case,
faith leaves otherwise well-intentioned people incapable of thinking
rationally about many of their deepest concerns; at worst, it
is a continuous source of human violence. Even now, many of us
are motivated not by what we know but by what we are content merely
to imagine. Many are still eager to sacrifice happiness, compassion,
and justice in this world, for a fantasy of a world to come. These
and other degradations await us along the well-worn path o piety.
Whatever our religious differences may mean for the next life,
they have only one terminus in this one-a future of ignorance
and slaughter.
We live in societies that are still constrained
by religious laws and threatened by religious violence. What is
it about us, and specifically about our discourse with one another,
that keeps these astonishing bits of evil loose in our world?
We have seen that education and wealth are insufficient guarantors
of rationality. Indeed, even in the West, educated men and women
still cling to the blood-soaked heirlooms of a previous age. Mitigating
this problem is not merely a matter of reining in a minority of
religious extremists; it is a matter of finding approaches to
ethics and to spiritual experience that make no appeal to faith,
and broadcasting this knowledge to everyone.
p224
This world is simply ablaze with bad ideas. There are still places
where people are put to death for imaginary crimes-like blasphemy-and
where the totality of a child's education consists of his learning
to recite from an ancient book of religious fiction. There are
countries where women are denied almost every human liberty, except
the liberty to breed. And yet, these same societies are quickly
acquiring terrifying arsenals of advanced weaponry. If we cannot
inspire the developing world, and the Muslim world in particular,
to pursue ends that are compatible with a global civilization,
then a dark future awaits all of us.
The contest between our religions is zero-sum.
Religious violence is still with us because our religions are
intrinsically hostile to one another. Where they appear otherwise,
it is because secular knowledge and secular interests are restraining
the most lethal improprieties of faith. It is time we acknowledged
that no foundation exists within the canons of Christianity, Islam,
Judaism, or any of our other faiths for religious tolerance and
religious diversity.
p226
We do not know what awaits each of us after death, but we know
that we will die. Clearly, it must be possible to live ethically-with
a genuine concern for the happiness of other sentient beings-without
presuming to know things about which we are patently ignorant.
Sam Harris page
Index of Website
Home
Page